This was written in conjunction with the seminar I participated in at Yale summer 2010, after a lot of reading about libertarian philosophy and economics, and was for an independent study I did here at Houghton that summer/fall.
Caution: it's ridiculously long :p
The main things that I have been reading
seem to indicate that the libertarian question focuses around one basic point:
what is the proper role of government in society? This includes the areas of
economics, military, welfare, and is a question of if modern government really
is of the people and for the people, as so many modern democratic constitutions
claim, or if it is in fact more of a socialistic government comprised of people
who care more about their own political gains of power and wealth than of the
people they profess to represent.
My first reading was the Declaration of
Independence. I thought that would be a good way to start a seminar on liberty,
since it was the document that officially made the break for American liberty.
After learning somewhat about the British view of the American Revolution last
semester, reading the declaration made me wonder – were the people of America
objecting, actually, to British rule? Or was it more the policies that they
disagreed with? This was my question as I read more of the readings in this
course: do liberals believe that the government should be small on principle,
or is it that they don’t believe government is trustworthy and so try to limit
its size to protect themselves? I found part of the answer in Thomas Paine’s
“Common Sense”, when he asks “How came the king by a power which the people are
afraid to trust, and always obliged to check?” This seemed to indicate that the
power held by governments was not one that they necessarily agreed with or
wanted to have over them, but was instead one that they would prefer to be
without. In fact, the basis of Paine’s argument that a monarchial power was
evil pointed to not just that the government was too big, but that it
was wrong altogether.
From this
I gather that there are two basic thoughts of liberals in these readings –
firstly, that government must be ‘self-government’; as JS Mill said, “the rule
[not] of a person by himself, but of each by all the rest”. This also agrees
with Paine’s argument that a monarchy or king who holds absolute power is
wrong. The second is that even self-government must be checked. This is the
argument for a small government. In the seminar, one of the repeated themes was
that when government interferes with private life, especially in the economic
realm, the people suffer. It becomes a case of ‘the people’ vs. ‘the
government’, which defeats the purpose of the government functioning to protect
the people.
An example given was the Tongass National Forest,
the largest temperate rainforest in the world. A West Virginia-sized piece of
land in Alaska, there are many natural resources available in it. One of these
is timber, and the US government has a logging operation running in the forest.
The problem occurs with the question “Who owns the Tongass?” The answer is
“everybody, nobody, and the government.” Since the government is the only party
out of those three that can practically do anything with the Tongass, (it is
not feasible for every American to head out there and log, etc,) the logging
operation is run only at the efficiency the government can produce. The
interested parties are the logging companies, who like having the government
roads made for them, congress, which likes the PAC money donated by the logging
companies, and the US Forestry Service, who gets jobs from Congress, and makes
the roads for the loggers. This all works together in a cycle of getting
jobs and money, while no one’s concern is that the procedures used are
environmentally healthy, conducive to regeneration in the Tongass, or anything
else – including the money, which the taxpayers pour into congress to keep the
cycle going, without receiving any noticeable benefit from the logging
business.
This example shows the immense waste
inherent in government business. If the Tongass were privately owned, if the
logging companies had to be competitive in order to get the job, if the owners
were concerned about the land and farsighted enough to look ahead and see the
importance of environmentally-sound logging practices, if the wood were being
sold on a free market to buyers who would use it in free trade, then the land
would be given good stewardship to ensure more production in the future, the
taxpayers would not be burdened, the government would not be spread into things
it was never constitutionally designed to do, and the entire system would be
better off. This is the kind of economics they taught at the seminar.
The 10-part video series by Milton
Friedman, “Free to Choose,” also focused largely on privatized economics. His
argument focuses on the waste inherent in government, and bases his opinions
off of the Declaration of Independence and Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations. He
believes that centralization of government is extremely dangerous, and that the
people must work very hard to be free, since the natural gravitation of any
government is towards expansion of power and centralization. The opposite of
this centralization is what Adam Smith noticed creates wealth – division of labor.
Smith’s observations were key in Friedman’s argument, as he argues that the
government is not a capable manager of the money of the people; that the people
should manage their own money. This is his belief on the separation of powers:
that decentralization would actually create
wealth, since the people would be ‘free to choose’ where they spent their
money, and what investments they wanted to make.
One of the real-life examples that I
found to be most thought provoking in the seminar was actually so real life it
was unintentional. One of the other students was saying that she made money
cleaning houses for people, but it was all under the table. Since there was no
requirement for minimum wage people could afford to hire her, and she had a job
she would not have otherwise had. We had been talking about the detrimental
effect minimum wage and labor unions/job security has on the economy, and the
point was all but proved when one of the professors jokingly said “well, I’d
hire you if you’d do a good job and I wouldn’t have to pay you minimum wage!”
It was intended as a side comment, but I saw it was proving the point: if he
could hire her at less than minimum wage, it would be good for him. If she had
no job security, then it would be incentive for her to do a good job. If she
did a good job, then he would keep her in his employ. It was neat to see an
instance where the theory we had been talking about actually had an example.
The example they officially gave was the Supreme Court case of Muller vs. Oregon, in which a law
intended to protect woman by limiting their hours actually took away jobs from
these women who worked in laundromats. The owners of the laundromats hired men
instead, who did not have limits on the number of hours worked and thus were
more profitable. The point of the illustration was that government interference
often has long-term, unintended side effects, which was in fact one of the main
themes of the seminar.
As an example of how business can
flourish when given the freedom, one of the professors used the Underwriters
Laboratory. Founded by insurance companies to test products that are to be
insured, it is a symbol of an electrical appliance that can be trusted. The
professor teaching this actually bit down on the power cord of a projector in
the room while it was on, to demonstrate his faith in the Laboratory. Since
they are not government owned and therefore are competitive, they have every
motive to only give their symbol to products they know to be safe. Therefore, the people know they can trust the
company so buy those products, and both parties flourish: the purchasers,
because they get a good product, and the company, because they have customers.
One of the big questions I had about the
libertarian argument concerns free market: if it is such a good thing, then why
doesn’t it always prevail? Why do governments naturally come to be more
controlling of the market, even in cases where the government is a democracy
and claims to have the best interest of the people in mind? With the free
market comes another question: doesn’t this allow for great stratification of
resources? Isn’t it possible – or even likely – that equality would not
prevail? The questions that concerned equality were some of the ones that
dissatisfied me the most with the libertarian argument, and throughout the
seminar I did not feel that they were adequately answered.
The question of the free market is one
that I am still wrestling with. From the perspective they offered at the
seminar, the idea of curtailing the free market was absolutely senseless. The
argument was given from a strictly economic standpoint, where yield minus cost
equals economic profit or loss. Where the revenue is greater than the cost, new
value has been created. They used the example of a man starting a restaurant:
If he spends $80,000.00 in labor, electricity, space, food, etc. and brings in
$100.000.00, then he has taken the value of the finished product to the
consumer minus the value of the raw goods and made the economy $20,000.00
better off. This is the value of the capitalist; he stimulates the economy.
There is no such thing as too much profit, as long as the profit is made in a
non-coercive, fair manner of free and voluntary exchange.
By its very nature, the more profit is made
the more wealth is created in a nation. Resources are multiplied by creativity,
and everyone is economically better off. In addition, if the economy is driven
by profit and loss, resources will be channeled into the most profitable areas.
This would eliminate the issue of wasted resources – if everyone looked out
only for their own best interests, the overall profit margin would be greater.
The general rule was that every endeavor should be subject to profit and loss –
no one should be taxed at a higher rate because they make high profits, and
people who are losing money should not have money poured into their failing
system.
They also pointed out that a strictly
free-market economy would encourage competition. New products would be offered,
since everyone would be trying to get an edge over every other person, and the
market – what sold and what didn’t – would determine who won the battle for
consumer dollars. The uncertainty in the market is precisely what keeps it
alive – the people doing the marketing cannot know exactly what it is that the
consumers want, and as such try producing a wide variety of new products. This
was the model given for a healthy market: many creative minds working to
out-perform one another, the consumer benefiting from a wide selection of products,
and the capitalist free to make a profit from his hard work.
For the most part, I agreed with this
argument. It made sense that people are by nature selfish, and would try to
make money. Having made money it is spent, and the economy is improved. However,
I remain unconvinced that in a society so driven by the market, the social
order would not suffer. It seems as though it would instead encourage a rather
Hobbsian state-of-nature atmosphere, where each was in a war against all. That,
of course, would not encourage free trade; warfare would quickly ensue. It
remains, then, to be seen if it is possible to have a civil society paired with
a free market.
The case for a libertarian civil society
was the core of what I saw to be the libertarian argument – at the same time
its strongest and weakest point. At the seminar, they vacillated between
allowing for limited restrictions on society to arguing that there is a sort of
spontaneous order that occurs in nature that would take care of the
problem. The latter I could not believe;
if for no other reason the killing fields of the twentieth century would prove
to me that men do not naturally live in harmony with one another. At the same
time, there is the argument that any peace that comes about in this world can
be attributed to a kind of spontaneous order. The argument was not that God
does not exist or does not play a role in human life, but instead that people
do not naturally make peace for each other. However, I find that argument to be
slightly less than convincing, because the point can be taken that any peace
that comes about in the world is a result of human endeavor. The peace summits
of international leaders are not forced upon the leaders of free countries; it
is a voluntary attempt to bring peace to the world. The argument is not that
God does not play any part in what goes on in the world; it is instead that
even if He does, it is an issue of the people who still are trying to make
peace. This still counts as spontaneous order, since the order is not coercive.
This is the part that bothers me the
most. The laws of nature are not contradictory, and yet it seems that even
while there is the issue that Hobbes brings up of the natural state being one
of war, there is at the same time the state we now find the world in – one of
welfare, social care, and attempts to bring peace to all people. Are these
international leaders truly concerned only with their own economic welfare? In
terms of overall politics, are the efforts truly only an economic attempt to
further one’s own self? That does not even address the issue of country – do
the leaders want the best for their countries out of a sense of patriotism, or
is it instead simply a personal, economic concern for their own salaries and
safe homes?
If the argument of each wanting only their
personal wellbeing holds sound, then why is there social welfare? I can see
what the motivation would be for some parts of a government – for example, it
is expedient for a government to have a strong military to protect its citizens
so the citizens will continue to pay taxes instead of being captured by a
foreign power and paying taxes elsewhere. A military is an economically sound practice
of protecting a valuable investment. What about the case, then, of a government
program like Medicaid? It seems like a rather long stretch to say that there is
an investment in loyalty and patriotism that the government can justify. After
all, even if the people who are benefitted directly by government welfare
programs are dedicated to the system that is giving them handouts and would
vote for the people who establish such principles, there is still the
consideration of all the people who are paying the taxes and putting into the
economy the money that is being sucked out by these people who are not adding
to the economic system. Since these are the capitalists, the ones whom this
free market is supposed to be benefiting, it seems rather counter-productive to
penalize them for their hard work. And yet, this is the natural trend of
government; it naturally moves toward being more and more socialistic and
providing programs for people who are in need.
The problem in society is the apparent
contradiction of innately selfish people, who really want to help each other,
faced with the practical realization that instead of helping one another, we often
kill each other. Is this an issue of wanting to hurt each other but having some
inward compulsion to make peace instead? History does not seem to indicate
anything of the sort. Do we inherently want to kill each other, and face the
world alone? If that was truly the case, then there would be no governments,
since no one is forcing the world to have structured governments – yet the
overwhelming majority of people in the world are ruled by some form of
government. In order, then, to accurately determine the structure of
government, it is necessary to understand human nature and the motives that
drive us.
The state of nature as Hobbes portrayed
it is one in which the people, despite any given geographical or familial
relations, do not in fact care for each other but are in opposition with each
other. The modern form of the state of nature is the capitalist ideal: a world
dependent wholly upon the work and independent intelligence of individuals. In
the same way, just as there is a tendency among humans to develop a government
to encourage working together and bringing a measure of security, modern
governments tend to take this a step further into the realm of using social,
governmental welfare to ensure that security. For some reason, although humans
seem to be by nature selfish, there is an ever-present trend of trying to bail
people out of their difficulties.
If the libertarian argument is true, then
there should be no need for a government to worry about taking too much care of
a people. Instead, the people should be concerned that the government does not,
in fact, actually care about them. The issue is one of contradictions, because
it is the people, working against themselves, that make a government. In a
democracy, oppressive government is made up of people who are themselves
oppressed by the government. It makes no sense that they would impose heavy
restrictions upon the country, because they would also necessarily be binding
themselves. That brings me back to the question: why, if human nature is to
kill all others, do they care enough to bail people out? Is there something
about human nature that was missed when Hobbes wrote Leviathan? Laws do not contradict themselves; human nature is what
it is.
The answer I have come to is that the
issue is not one of human concern for others, but is in fact an ultimate power
struggle. Through wanting to make themselves appear a certain way, governmental
leaders do things that look compassionate or merciful in order to maintain
international appearances. It is a worldwide trend of trying to impress others
in an effort to appear more powerful. For instance, the major money given in
supposed charity to people in need is actually more of an effort to appear charitable, protection given to
the defenseless is instead to maintain a reputation of care in order to gain
the goodwill and support of other nations. Such support is critical for ease of
international trading, economic growth, and so on; therefore we have arrived
back at the conclusion that the motivating concern of kindnesses is actually
economic and self-centered.
This is that part of the libertarian
argument that I do not have a problem with. Instead of attempting to prove that
there are in fact good intentions in the world, libertarians instead simply
admit that everyone is perfectly self-motivated and that far from having kind
intentions, humans are instead working for their own economic interest. In fact,
this is one of my favorite things about the libertarian argument, and that part
which I thought was best presented in the seminar. There is no pretense of good
will, or supposed care, but instead there is honesty of intentions, which I
find rare and refreshing to find. I would almost rather know that that someone
really is not looking out for me and know their motive, then be deceived into
thinking that they really have my best interest at heart.
The part of the libertarian argument
that I really do not like ad have trouble accepting is that humans can actually
live this way. As strong as the argument is that there are in fact no
un-selfish motives; that humans are by nature completely selfish and economics
are the only motives in life, I find it impossible to believe. The reading that
convinced me of this was, interestingly enough, Atlas Shrugged – the very book that set out to prove that the ideal
form of government was the strictly economical, capitalist one that I have been
describing. I found that book to be an interesting mixture of contradictions
and impossibilities, while parts of it were also very compelling. However, the
book at its very core contradicts itself: the tenement upon which the book
rests is that the brilliant leaders who are withdrawing themselves from the
scene of the world are causing it to collapse because of their complete
rationality – a rather egotistical, if not entirely inaccurate view of what
would happen if people no longer poured their lives into their work.
However, despite Ayn Rand’s almost
desperate attempt to show a world in which the ultimate ideal is objective,
unemotional selfishness; a system of government in which people do not care for
each other as anything more than a means to economic profit, I am unconvinced
that she actually achieved this goal. The central character, Dagny Taggart, is
portrayed as a woman who has streamlined her life into her work and nothing
else, who cares for nothing but the advancement of her railroad. In many ways,
this is well shown – Dagny’s creativity in circumventing the obstacles put in
her way by the increasingly socialistic government, her fantastic work ethic,
and never-ending perseverance make her a good example of a driven capitalist.
However, her character is inconsistent
in her relationships with men. During the course of the book, she has affairs
with three different men, none of which are for the purpose of economic benefit
or furthering her railroad. Thus, while she is in so many ways an ideal
libertarian, the book does not convince me that the wholly free-market economy
system really does work. It didn’t even work for the characters in the book!
Since it is more likely that a person would write about something that could
not happen rather than allowing things to happen in the book that weaken the
argument, I am unconvinced that Rand does an adequate job of proving the
libertarian argument. She outlines a good case, but the proof is lacking.
That being said, I think the book is
rather realistic, since I don’t think that libertarians are entirely correct in
their argument. The very human emotions that are inescapable in the book are
similarly integral in real life. The protests of the characters that they do
nothing for the sake of another are drowned out by the sacrifices they make for
those they care about. If the argument was that a society need not care for
those they do not know, then that would be okay. However, since they claim to
not sacrifice for anyone and then do
that very thing, I am unimpressed.
Atlas
Shrugged contradictions aside, I think that the libertarian
argument was summed up in its strengths and weaknesses rather well in that
book. They believe in capitalism and free market. That was what the book was
advocating. The problem with the libertarian position seems to be primarily
this issue with people ending up actually caring for each other, when in a
perfect libertarian society no one would care for anyone else. This weakness in
the libertarian argument was also in the book. If Ayn Rand had been purposed to
write a book on libertarianism, then she would have done rather well. That, I
think, is why the sponsors of the seminar recommended the book so highly. As
Randian philosophy, it falls a bit short. For summing up the libertarian
argument, it is probably the best that could be done.
The question of individual versus
collective liberty is one of the major arguments in libertarianism. Are people
in fact so interconnected that anything one person does, another person is
similarly affected? According to Bastiat, in What is Seen and What is Not Seen, it would appear to be so. His
argument – also highlighted in Henry Hazlitt’s book Economics in One Lesson – is that when one action is performed, it
has either negative or positive consequences on the rest of society. The
example used was of a broken window: if a window is broken, people see the
money that is being spent by the man who owned the window at the window maker’s
shop. This is considered to be economic stimulation – it is money that is being
spent, and as such, the economy prospers. However, the point drawn out by both
Bastiat and Hazlitt is that while it is true that the man spends his money at
the glaziers, he does not spend it elsewhere. The natural function of money is
to be spent, and unless the man would have never spent his money, having a
broken window does not boost the economy. It simply redirects where the money
is spent.
The reading of Randy Barnett’s “The
Moral Foundations of Modern Libertarianism” gave a fairly concise summary of
libertarian belief. Libertarians recognize existence and value of individual
persons, and as such they place value on the ability of all persons to live and
pursue happiness. However, the belief in the pursuit of happiness, it must be remembered, is different that a guarantee of the results. If it would
make a person happy to kill someone else, that does not justify the action: the
person killed is not free to live and pursue happiness themselves, so the
would-be killer must restrain themselves since their wish is a ‘less-basic’
right than that of the victim. That is an extreme example, though, and the
point being made at the seminar was that it is possible for nearly all to
pursue happiness without depriving others of the same. For the few that are not
covered under that ‘nearly all’ I do not have an answer – it is a question of
equality, and as I mentioned before, the libertarian argument on equality was
not brought to a satisfactory conclusion at the seminar, and I still do not
know what they would say in such a case.
With liberty to do as one wishes,
restriction of government, and economic equality discussed, I now want to
explore just one more issue of the libertarian argument. This question is
simply if libertarianism is actually practical to accept as a worldview or
philosophy of government. The apparent benefits are that there is economic
prosperity, if the theory holds true, since free market is encouraged and
flourishes. Freedom given to citizens to do as they please translates into
people who work harder, since they are doing what they actually want to be
doing instead of being coerced into doing something they have no interest in.
This is good for a government, since the nation is wealthier, which grants
power and prestige. High international standing transfers into more investments
from other countries, and the economy prospers further. This is the purpose libertarians have for believing
in the free market. The drawbacks are that there is necessarily complete
ruthlessness. The thought struck me when I was at the seminar, then it became
somewhat buried with all the other things I was learning, only to resurface
when I read Atlas Shrugged. The lack
of concern over the welfare of others bothered me, but as I thought more about
the issue, and continue to think, I am becoming more and more convinced that this
lack of concern is necessary in a free government. In fact, it seems to me that
this is the very issue that is at the root of government over-interference: too
many kind intentions. After debating what the causes of motivation are for
kindnesses, I have come to the conclusion this is in fact the part of human
nature in government that the libertarian argument does not take into account.
In order for the
libertarian government to work, the people must be completely heartless, caring
for nothing but their own economic gain. If this is the case, then as far as I
can tell, the libertarian government would have a chance at success. However,
as sound as the policies might be, there is no room in this argument for
natural human affection for one another. A true libertarian would not care for
their parents or children, much less someone who was not related to them.
Clearly this is not the case; a cursory examination of any civilization will
disprove any theory that people do not form relationships with each other.
The fact that
libertarian politics do not allow for gentleness in character does not
necessarily mean they are wrong; indeed I have no reason to believe that
charity is meant to be the responsibility of government. In history, whenever
government takes upon itself to provide for the needs of the poor they end up
taking over and the citizens, far from ending up with more freedom and care, instead have no freedom and
only so much care as the government decides to provide at the time – a most
precarious position indeed, and not at all the libertarian definition of
limited government and freedom!
If, then, it is not
wrong for libertarians to have a ‘no charity’ policy, does that mean there are
no objections to implementing it as my governmental policy of choice? I remain
unconvinced. My thought is that even if it is not wrong, there is little to no chance that it would actually work. The
reasoning behind this is straightforward – even the best politics would be hard
pressed to overcome human nature. Therefore, even if the libertarian argument
is solid, the humans implementing the policies are not, and that is where the
difficulty arises. It doesn’t matter how good the logic is behind the argument,
if it doesn’t work in real life there is no use in promoting it.
I heard a lot of
arguments from people who believed very strongly in libertarianism, and the
readings were also (with the notable exception of Plato and his rather
communistic city) mostly slanted in the direction of less government meaning a
better society. I learned a lot about what the libertarian argument was, thus
fulfilling my objective for taking the seminar and going through the readings,
thinking about what libertarianism was. Still, even after hearing and reading a
disproportionally large number of pros without having the opposing arguments, I
cannot totally believe the libertarian argument. I think a part of that is my
conclusion that it would not work in practicality – that human nature, despite
everything that Hobbes said about our wanting to kill each other, and despite
the terrible genocides that do occur in the world, also bends toward something
less than absolute austerity in the way common people actually deal with each
other. Certainly there are broken homes, hurting people, and terrible things
that happen in people’s lives. However, most people do not have the strong,
idealistic principles required to be a pure libertarian – they will form
attachments with other humans, take compassion on someone, or be less than
cutthroat in business. If all people were cold and emotionless and fanatically
devoted to their principles, libertarianism might work. As the world stands, my
conclusion is that it is not a practical philosophy because such
characteristics are not, in fact, human nature, and as such a different
philosophy of politics is required.
In my opinion there is no perfect government. The reason being is that government, whether monarchial, communistic, democratic, or republican is made up of individuals, and individuals are conscious, thinking beings. Given a situation where a government is led by wise, God-fearing people the nation and thereby the people will prosper, but if that same nation is led by corrupt individuals trouble is no doubt impending.
ReplyDeleteThat being said, I do think that certain governments have shown themselves to be superior to others, if only by the fact that they limit the amount of damage a corrupt individual can do.
This is the main attribute that compels me to agree on certain issues with the libertarian. The libertarian understands that when an individual is left to his own inspiration, which we can see in any everyday occurance is usually to gain profit, the entirety of society benefits. In an economic sense the Libertarian system makes sense, but the problem arises from one of Libertarianism' most basic tenets. Whatever a man does is right. A society can NOT survive in that fashion.
So in summary, I agree that a true libertarian state would be impossible, but I also say that if you take certain parts of libertarian methodology and utilize it you can benefit any system.
P.S: Sorry this is so pathetic in comparison.
I do agree with you on the summary - basically, if humans were perfect, then it would work, or something along those lines.
ReplyDeleteAnd I wouldn't say that's so pathetic ... after all, you didn't spend six months on it :p